Sunday, 21 July 2013

Anxious "Emotional" Doubt

In this series I’m trying to help Christians understand how doubts about their religious beliefs work. In the first post I said that there were different kinds of doubt and that it’s very important to discern which kind of doubt it is you might be struggling with. Factive “Intellectual” Doubt and Anxious “Emotional” Doubt are the two kinds of doubt I picked out for attention. Having unpacked Factive doubt last time, it’s time to address Anxious Doubt.

Anxious Doubt is far more “slippery” than its Factive cousin. While I want to move away from the “emotional” label, anxious doubt does, of course, fundamentally involve emotions. And it’s for that reason that we might be less clear about the nature of our doubt if it’s anxious in kind. There can be a certain “murkiness” to emotions. We don’t always have a conscious grasp of what our emotions are “about”. Sometimes they’re ambiguous (you know that you have some affection for the new girl at the club but is it you getting too excited about a close friendship or is it love – the real deal?) And sometimes it’s just that we’ve never given them much thought. They’ve moved and enthralled us and we’ve never been in a place where we’ve stood back and thought about what’s driving them, or we haven’t even noticed them. It’s possible, as a result, that our doubt can be driven by the emotion of anxiety without us being aware of it. So let’s explore the nature of this sort of doubt so we might be in a place to see it in ourselves if it’s present. Anxious doubt “sounds” a lot like this:

(A) I’m thinking about taking Biblical studies next year. But what if I discover that the gospels are riddled with contradictions? What if I lose my faith?

(B) Mackie’s argument from evil makes a lot of sense to me. What if there are no good responses to it? What if he has refuted Christianity?

(C) I’ve prayed the sinner’s prayer many times before but what if I didn’t do it properly? Might I not have really meant it? Maybe I’m not actually a Christian?

You might notice that with these sorts of doubts, the object of concern is not something thought to be actually the case. Rather it’s something thought to be possibly the case.  

In example (A) the doubter does not think there actually are contradictions in the Bible. Rather he/she is scared that there might be. Similarly with (B), the doubt isn’t about actually having found no adequate response to Mackie’s argument, it’s about possibly finding no response. In (C), again, the doubter isn’t mulling over some concretely present objection to the reality of their salvation, he/she is just fretting over mere possibilities. If phrases like, “what if?”, “there might be”, and “maybe there is”, often crop up in our doubts that’s a strong clue that we’re dealing with anxious doubt, not factive doubt.

So that’s a start. But we need to get clearer on how all this ties into anxiety.

Anxiety Basics

Anxiety is a complex, multi-faceted phenomenon but we can nail a basic starting point for our discussion. Anxiety is essentially the fear of dreadful possibilities being actualised. If regular fear is the kind of fear you’d experience confronted with a lion, anxiety is the fear experienced over the possibility that a lion might be nearby. It’s the kind of fear only creatures capable of self-awareness can experience. The fear of a circumstance we can picture in our mind, even if its reality isn’t right in front of us. The “picture in our mind”, though, isn’t always consciously articulated. Sometimes it is. Sometimes we consciously wonder whether, say, we prayed the sinner’s prayer correctly, and anxiety builds in response. But other times our anxiety “goes ahead of us” and detects fearful possibilities implicit in a situation that we haven’t consciously seen. You see an article criticising your favourite preacher and before you’ve even clicked the link, anxiety puts you “on guard”.

In itself, though, anxiety isn’t bad. In fact sometimes it’s totally appropriate, called for, and warranted by a situation. Like all emotions, anxiety can be appropriate in some circumstances, and inappropriate in others. Take anger as a comparison case.

Your friend has just spilt the contents of his cup over your table. Should you be angry? Is anger called for in this circumstance? Well, that will depend on a few things. If the liquid is a fine wine – it’s a waste of a good drop and bound to stain too – you might have more grounds for anger than if it was only spilt water. But then anger also crucially involves the perception of wilful destruction or neglect by someone else toward something you value. So if your friend innocently slipped and knocked it over, anger would be unwarranted. But if instead your friend knocked it over just to spite you, anger may well be called for. It all depends on what your anger is “about”. It depends on whether your anger properly represents the “evaluative situation”. And so it is with all emotions. All emotions are “about” states of affairs. They are appropriate in some circumstances and inappropriate in others dependent on whether they have properly captured the essence of what’s going on in regards to your values.

So what is anxiety “about?” When is it called for and when is it inappropriate? In answering this question, we can get closer to figuring out how to understand the anxious doubt we might have about our faith.

We’ve already said that anxiety is the fear of dreadful possibilities being actualised. For the Christian this is (for example) the fear of the possibility that we have bought into a lie, or that we’re self-deceived, or that we weren’t sincere enough in our initial conversion. The anxiety is, roughly, about those possibilities (hypothetical though they may be). But we need to go deeper to explore whether these fears are appropriate or not.

What Makes Anxiety Appropriate or Not?

Let’s start with a non-religious example. Most of us typically care about our families. Our parents, siblings, or spouses mean a great deal to us. And though we don’t like to, we can imagine possible scenarios where bad things happen to them. It would truly be horrific, for instance, to wake up one morning and find that our loved ones have been attacked by intruders during the night. That, we would say, is definitely a dreadful possibility. But note that most of us are not, when we wake in the morning, anxious to find out whether our family are still alive and well. It generally doesn’t occur to us to consider that they might not be. We just expect our family to be fine. And that’s normal and right.

If, without some special circumstantial reason, you did feel anxious about your family in the morning, that wouldn’t be normal. Indeed, if you spent two hours every night sorting out 20 separate locks on each door or window just to ensure nobody could gain entry uninvited, you would have a problem. That level of vigilance is extreme and uncalled for. Think about that behaviour; if you knew a person who did just that, what would you say to them?

“Dan are you sure you’re okay? Do you not think 20 locks on your door is too much? One is enough.”
“You might say that, Jess, but even a decent quality lock can give way after a little while. What if an attacker is committed enough to get through it? You need back-ups.”
“Yeah but... Dan, they’d have to have a professional team to break through more than a few.”
“And seeing as those teams exist, how can I leave my family at jeopardy?”
“I don’t think those teams operate around here, Dan. And I doubt they care that much about your house.”
“Regular citizens sometimes are targeted, Jess. It’s a fact. You need to be prepared.”

If you approach that conversation like Jess above, it’s likely that you’ll not get very far. Notice her strategy. She observed that Dan was looking for assurance that he could protect his family, and she tried to offer reasons that would give that to him. Look, that possibility you are fearing is not a realistic possibility at all, she claimed. But what if the problem is precisely that Dan doesn’t have realistic expectations or desires at all?

Sometimes people talk to their friends and let them know that they are worrying about a particular matter, and often, from the friend’s perspective, their worrying appears clearly needless or overblown, even if understandable. There are typically two kinds of advice friends give in these situations to calm the other person. Here’s the first kind, “look it’s not that big a deal really, so what if it goes wrong?”, “even if that did happen, you would still get it done so don’t worry”, “there are more important things in life than that, I wouldn’t concern yourself with it.” Here is the second kind: “there’s no point worrying about it – there’s nothing you can do”, “worrying won’t help, it’s out of your hands,” “too late to do anything now, no need to torture yourself with worry.” Both sets of advice aim to show that the anxiety and worry in the situation is inappropriate. In them we find clues as to what it is for anxiety to be appropriate or not.

The logic that’s implicit in the first set seems to be that anxiety is only appropriate for important matters. That is, you shouldn’t worry about trivial, inconsequential things. Worry about such lesser concerns is a waste of time. Anxiety, then, we might say, is only appropriate if it is in proportion to the importance of the thing worried about. What about the second set? Notice that in the second set, the appropriateness of anxiety seems to be bound up with whether the person has any meaningful control of the situation. If you can’t affect the matter, there is no point worrying. If it’s out of your hands, worrying about the situation is wasteful and unproductive. The clues behind this set of advice seem to reveal that anxiety is only appropriate if it is in proportion to the degree of control we have over the thing worried about it.

Jesus, in fact, uses both kinds of advice in his sermon-on-the-mount teaching on anxiety;

“Therefore I tell you, do not be anxious about your life, what you will eat or what you will drink, nor about your body, what you will put on. Is not life more than food, and body more than clothing?” (Matthew 6: 25)

He starts off with advice representative of the first set. He claims, essentially, that clothing, food, and drink are not important enough to warrant the sort of anxiety his audience was prone to having about those things. He then moves on to challenge their sense of control over these concerns;

“Look at the birds of the air: they neither sow nor reap nor gather into barns, and yet your heavenly Father feeds them. Are you not of more value than they? And which of you by being anxious can add a single hour to his span of life?” (Matthew 6: 26-27)

He doubly challenges their sense of control by pointing out how useless their anxiety is (it does not actually help them live any longer) and by teaching that ultimately it is God who is in control of their well-being. You matter to God, Jesus teaches, and he is looking out for you.

So we can combine the findings of both sets of advice to get a general statement about what makes anxiety appropriate or not: anxiety is only appropriate in proportion to the degree of control a person has over, and the degree of importance of, the object of anxiety.

We can now examine why it is exactly that Dan’s need to have so many locks on his house is inappropriate. We can ask whether Dan’s anxiety is proportional to the degree of importance his family’s safety has for him and proportional to the degree of control Dan actually has over his family’s safety. In regard to the first question about importance, we will probably say that, yes, his anxiety is proportionate. His family will be one of Dan’s central life concerns. This is not a trivial thing Dan is concerned about. It does indeed matter very much whether his family is safe or not. What makes Dan’s anxiety inappropriate is that it is entirely disproportionate to the amount of control he actually has to ensure their safety. What Dan needs is to “let go” of his false sense of control and responsibility. We’ll come back to this need to let go.

You might object at this stage that clearly Dan does in reality have the very level of control that he senses he has. After all, Dan does have the ability to put that many locks on his door. He can, if he wants, control his family’s safety to that extent and seems to be doing so. This is a good observation. We could, in response, say that, in all likelihood, Dan’s sense of control is not actually satisfied by the reality of the situation. We could say that, even though Dan can put 20 locks on his door, plausibly, he still isn’t satisfied. He feels like he could do with 30, or more. He is still anxious. This is a realistic portrait of how Dan might feel but nonetheless, we don’t need it. Say that Dan is totally satisfied with the 20 locks. We can still point out that his sense of control needs readjusting.

We can say that the problem with Dan is that his sense of control is out of sync with the level of fruitful control that he truly possesses. Note that past a certain level of taking control, additional efforts have increasingly little pay-off. When you start off, the pay-offs are big, but they gradually dwindle in significance as you increase vigilance. There is a big difference, for instance, between having zero locks on your door and having one. In putting the one lock there, you greatly increase your home’s security. There may also be a similarly big gain in going from one lock to two. But eventually, the level of security you’ll gain for the effort of putting in another extra lock will be negligible. How much difference is there, really, between 19 locks and 20? Almost every intruder who is determined to get through 19 will also get through 20 – there’ll only be one or two perhaps in the whole world for whom just that twentieth lock would be a deterrent. It gets to the point where exercising control to that level isn’t worth it any more.

Additionally, the effort of exercising that level of control will likely have detrimental effects in your life at large. Those two hours that Dan spends locking the house every night are two hours away from his spouse and kids. Such paranoid efforts could put considerable strain on his relationships. Dan’s behaviour negatively affects the very people he is doing all this to protect. His anxiety is indeed disproportionate to the level of fruitful control he possesses.

Bringing the Pieces Together

Let’s make an attempt to incorporate our findings so far into a fuller picture of anxiety.[1] When we develop the emotional habit of anxiety we develop an attunement toward potential threats to something. Like with Dan, let’s say this “something” is our family. In anxiety-attunement we become sensitive to possible dangers that could befall our family. And when in our attunement we feel a threat to our family through anxiety, we are motivated to protect our family. We are motivated to secure them against threat. When our anxiety-attunement is appropriate, it is a good thing. An attunement to threat to our family and a motivation to protect them is an essential part of caring for our family.

Our anxiety is inappropriate, on the other hand, when we are attuned to threats that are not worth being attuned to. Threats, for instance, to things that are not important. If we were attuned not to our family’s well-being, but, instead, to whether we have Sky+ TV or not, that would be a wasteful attunement. Attunement to threats that we cannot fruitfully control are also not worth having. It is pointless to be attuned to the threat of intruders breaking through 20 locks when there is very little one can fruitfully do about it.

That seems to be a good round-up of the key insights gained from examining Dan’s case.    

Dan’s case is, admittedly, a high-end anxiety case but it easier with such a case, as opposed to a more subtle one, to “see” and pick apart the nature of anxiety. Inappropriate anxious religious doubt, like all anxious doubt, will come in varying degrees of intensity and frequency, from mild to severe. Some people, we should note, have appropriate anxious religious doubt. (Dan might have good grounds to be anxious if he took his holiday on family to a lodge and found out upon arrival that there were no locks on the doors. Likewise, if a Christian has been given little or no reasonable, basic grounds for assurance that they are saved, or that Christianity is true, anxiety about those matters will likely be appropriate. And people in that situation should be encouraged to get that basic assurance. Most of what was said about factive doubt in the last post will apply if that’s you.) But I’m concerned in this post, as it turns out, with inappropriate anxious religious doubt. What can we say about that?

Let’s apply our analysis of anxiety to the case of religious doubt. Let’s say we are doubting the status of our salvation. We are thinking, “what if I didn’t say the prayer right at my conversion? What if I did but I didn’t fully mean it?” Our pastor assures us that there is no correct way to say the prayer (the Bible doesn’t even include a “sinner’s prayer”, he says). Regarding our sincerity, he assures us that you and I are two of the most devoted Christians of our age he knows. This is pretty good assurance. But we aren’t satisfied. We think “yeah but what if our outward devotion is just a mask concealing more confused motives? What if our pastor doesn’t know us very well? There may not be a sinner’s prayer in the Bible but God surely doesn’t accept just any old string of words as repentance – what if we didn’t pray properly?” At outside observer would probably wonder what actually would satisfy us.

But note, this is probably the sort of attitude you took to Dan in his conversation with Jess above. The extent of Dan’s desire to secure his family seemed unreasonable and insatiable. And that’s exactly what we concluded of him. His anxiety was not operating at a healthy level. His standard for assurance was not reasonably set. As such, reasonable grounds for assurance did not satisfy him. Jess was giving him good reasons not to worry, but he didn’t find them calming. Dan would only be satisfied by unreasonable grounds for assurance. He would be assured only if the possibility that intruders would break into his home was reduced to 0. What makes this level so unreasonable is that it is impossible to reduce risk to 0 or to approach 0 fruitfully. It is not worth being attuned to risk to this degree, as we noted. The same applies to religious doubt.

It is a possibility that you’re deceived about Christianity’s truth, or that you aren’t really saved (or whatever). You cannot reduce the risk of that being the case to 0. It is always possible to imagine some scenario where your greatest fear might be true after all. It is always possible that there’s some knock-down argument against Christianity you haven’t encountered yet. It is always possible that you’ve self-deceived yourself – that your motives aren’t pure and you didn’t truly repent. Seeking out near-infallible assurance is a fool’s errand. That sort of certainty just isn’t available to finite creatures like us. Although our faith is important, such that it is worth having some level of anxiety-attunement about it, it is not worth being anxiety-attuned to every slightest possible risk to our faith. We do not have fruitful control over those risks. If confidence in our faith depends on eradicating all those risks, confidence we will never have.

Gaining Proper Confidence

How is confidence attained, then, if it isn’t by seeking to assuage our anxious craving for absolute certainty? We should remember that this series is about analysis of the kinds of doubt rather than practical steps for handling doubt. But some basic pointers in the right direction have been offered. Here too, I humbly offer – as someone still making his way through anxious doubt – one very basic pointer. And it is indeed very basic. It is more like the end goal with virtually no comment as to how to arrive. People with highly habitual, intense anxious doubt in particular will find that much more by way of practical daily management needs to be said. You will have to find that sort of help elsewhere. Indeed, if your anxiety is quite life-hindering, it is worth your time doing further reading about it or seeing a counsellor. Sometimes the way our own particular anxiety functions includes very knotty, tangled, viciously circular thoughts that we will be very unlikely to set in order on our own.

Anyway, the basic end goal is this: letting go of ultimate control of our faith to God and trusting him with it.

We need to let go of our anxiety-attunements that are not worth having. We need to become de-attuned, de-sensitised to minute risks. This means, in effect, not reinforcing those attunements by seeking that infallible assurance when anxiety hits. The desire for that assurance is inappropriate and needs to be resisted. One must learn to cope not having absolute control of one’s faith. One must get used to living with that risk - used to giving over control to God. The more this is practised, the more those worthless attunements will phase out.  

This takes courage. In anxiety you feel a threat bear down on you. You are motivated to take action – to secure what you value. De-sensitising yourself in this way requires facing that threat square on and not trying to reduce it, resisting those motivations.   

As I’ve already quite clearly indicated, this will be much harder for some than others. For some, inappropriate anxious doubt is not a highly developed attunement as such but something more like an occasional episode. The result of an isolated mood, or “spill-over” from negative feelings toward some other circumstance. For others, this attunement will be well entrenched and difficult to lodge. My prayer is that as you grow in self-awareness to identify when your doubt is anxious in nature, you will find there an opportunity to grow in courage and trust in Christ.  


[1] This picture of anxiety, and the implicit picture of emotions generally that I’m working with, owes much to Helm, B. W. (2001). Emotional reason: Deliberation, motivation, and the nature of value. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

7 comments:

Josh Roe said...

Perhaps there is a stronger notion of anxiety that is helpful. Kierkegaard distinguishes between fear and anxiety. Fear is of something particular; whereas anxiety is not attached to any particular thing (Heidegger describes this as a kind of restlessness). This sense of anxiety resists attempts at control because there is 'nothing' to be resisted. Only when the nothing is made into something does it become a possible object of control. Alongside appropriate fear of a problem that can be addressed, anxiety can also open up the letting go of ultimate control. Thus anxiety could be faced, rather than used only insofar as it can be overcome.

Martin said...

Hi Josh, thanks for "stopping by!"

It might be that indeed there is another sort of anxiety that I haven't mentioned in this post. I am content, though, to address the sort I have mentioned for my purposes, as I think the sort I have mentioned is most common as a form of "emotional doubt."

But as an aside, then, what of this other Kierkegaardian or Heideggerian sense of anxiety? I think it certainly is possible to experience anxiety that seems quite disconnected from any object. I don't think this is the typical experience of anxiety though. So if one wanted to use this concept of anxiety to describe the general human condition, I would contest that use.

Still, some people surely experience something like that. And I guess for those people, if they have a truly inexplicable anxiety, it would be the case that they would have no control over it (except perhaps through drugs).

I think this does raise the interesting point that, in the typical case, even anxiety management itself can become an issue of control and thus further anxiety. One needs to let go of ultimate control even over one's own anxiety.

rolo said...

"Clap, Clap, Clap, Clap, Clap" goes my hands after reading your three posts on doubt.
While I enjoyed all of your posts, by far the most fascinating was this latest one on emotional doubt. Now any arguments about the nature of emotion aside, for now at least, your post on Anxious doubt offers an account of emotional doubt that is genuinely compelling and really gets at the fundamental issues. This is particularly evident in the story of Dan which you effectively use to illustrate both the nature of anxious doubt and why such doubt is inappropriate. Overall you get a smiley face. That said progress is fueled by disagreement.
To begin with, I'm a little disappointed by your choice to go along with the conventional emotional/intellectual doubt format. It's a format that's extremely simple to understand, but as you and I both know it's also incredibly misleading when it comes to understanding how doubt plays out in real life. In real life, the neat, tidy, and arbitrary divide between emotions and intellect is blurred if not nonexistent. It's very rare that someone whose emotionally secure and satisfied in their faith will be troubled by an intellectual objection to their faith for example. This is a pretty obvious objection
The issue is even more complicated than that, however. As we have also discussed, doubts don't simply spontaneously emerge out of a person's psyche. Oftentimes they can be triggered by seemingly benign forces such as a person's material reality or their social status. For instance, a person who grows up in a secure, fairly wealthy household may have more doubts about religion than a much poorer person since there is some evidence that possessing greater physical and financial security naturally lessens a person's attraction to religion. In the social realm, a person may start to have doubts about Christianity after they feel they've been ostracized from the Christian groups around them. This is precisely what happened to me. I had "intellectual objections" to Christianity before and was even dealing with some emotional issues, but the real trigger for my doubt was my social status within the Christian community. I could go on and on, but the point is that the age old intellectual/emotional doubt format simply doesn't offer a way to understand the way in which doubt plays itself out in real life. In many ways it's simply unhelpful in helping us deal with the problem of doubt.
In a somewhat related objection, I would say that another problem with not only your account, but also others is the fact that they don't deal with doubt as an epistemiological issue. Doubt by its very nature is a problem of epistemology; it is at its root a problem of how we can know what we know. Consequently, it cannot for example be divorced from issues related to when to give up a belief and when not to. When discussing doubt it seems as if many takes on it stop at the objection itself and don't deal with the issue of what to do if that objection doesn't go away. For example, if someone has a serious objection to whether or not Jesus was resurrected, but doesn't find a satisfactory answer to that objection should that person quit his or her faith and if not why not. Any effective response to doubt must provide a Christian epistemology that answers these questions.
I don't think I agree with presuppositionalism at least the Answers in Genesis variety, but I do think they have a point in trying to offer a complete Christian epistemology that can effectively deal with the epistemological issue of doubt.
As always sorry about the overly long comment. Twas a fascinating set of posts and I hope I provided useful fodder for discussion with my comment.

Martin said...

Hi Rolo, glad you enjoyed the post!

Regarding the intellectual/emotional set-up, that is something I take myself to have challenged (at least as it’s typically, simplistically set up), but that doesn’t come across strongly in these posts. In earlier drafts, I went into much more detail about why I was dropping the terms “intellectual” and “emotional” in favour of “factive” and “anxious” but I had so much content to fit in and the posts were getting so long (I’m pretty sure the anxious doubt post is my longest ever) that I decided to drop most of that part of the discussion. I definitely affirm, though, that doubt cannot be neatly separated into intellectual/emotional. For instance, some “intellectual” objections – typically those of a moral kind – are inescapably emotional too. I think I’ve mentioned to you before that I think the typically apologetic response of dismissing certain moral reactions of disgust to problem passages as merely “fallacious arguments from outrage” as simplistic and missing the point that some of our key moral beliefs are emotionally accessed.

I also agree with you that a person’s economic set-up and relational/social status affect Christian belief. (I might differ from you along similar lines to how we differ on emotions, in that you reach for language to describe these circumstances as “triggering” responses in the believers, but I’m tempted to talk more about how circumstances change the “meaning” that belief has for us. These are rough intuitions.)

I also agree that doubt and certainty are objects for inclusion in a broad epistemological theory, a theory I obviously haven’t offered here. And regarding your question of what one should do when, say, a resolution to a serious (factive) doubt about the resurrection isn’t to hand, well, I don’t know. These are interesting cases. I see in them something like an interpretive dilemma. Does one interpret the situation as calling for faithful patience in holding out, even longer, for an answer, or does one view interpret the situation as calling for abandon of the faith, calling it quits, recognising that one has given things enough time? There is often ambiguity in what sense to make of things, even if we recognise some cases where it could be simple, black & white.

carmen said...

I relate to scenario C. Doubting salvation. I get that a lot.

Martin said...

Hi Carmen, thanks for sharing. Yeah I think a lot of people really struggle with C. I hope you manage to work your way through it.

carmen said...

Thank you. Am glad your blog still going. Keep up the good work